Dictionary Definition
justice
Noun
2 the administration of law; the act of
determining rights and assigning rewards or punishments; "justice
deferred is justice denied" [syn: judicature]
3 a public official authorized to decide
questions bought before a court of justice [syn: judge, jurist, magistrate]
4 the United States federal department
responsible for enforcing federal laws (including the enforcement
of all civil rights legislation); created in 1870 [syn: Department
of Justice, Justice
Department, DoJ]
User Contributed Dictionary
Pronunciation
- IPA: //, /"dZVs.tIs/
Noun
- The state of being just or fair.
- The ideal of fairness, esp. with regard to the punishment of
wrongdoing.
- justice was served
- punishment of a person who wronged one
- to demand justice
- The civil power dealing with law.
- Ministry of Justice
- the justice system
- Ministry of Justice
- A judge of certain
courts. Also as a title.
- Chief Justice
- puisne justice
- Mr. Justice Krever
- puisne justice
- Chief Justice
Antonyms
Derived terms
Translations
state of being just or fair
- Croatian: pravo, pravda
- Czech: spravedlnost
- Danish: ret , retfærdighed
- German: Gerechtigkeit
- Hungarian: igazságosság, pártatlanság
- Italian: giustizia
- Kurdish: داد
- Polish: sprawiedliwość
- Slovene: pravica, pravičnost
punishment of a person who wronged one
- Croatian: pravda
- Czech: spravedlnost
- Danish: retfærdighed
- German: Gerechtigkeit
- Hungarian: igazságszolgáltatás
- Italian: giustizia
- Polish: sprawiedliwość
- Slovene: pravica
punishment of a person who wronged one
- Polish: sprawiedliwość
the civil power dealing with law
- Polish: sprawiedliwość
a judge of certain courts
- Polish: sędzia
- ttbc Albanian: drejtë
- ttbc Bulgarian: (1, 2, 3) справедливост , правда , право ; (4) правосъдие
- ttbc Catalan: justícia
- ttbc Chinese: 公義
- ttbc Dutch: gerechtigheid
- ttbc Esperanto: justeco (state of being just); justico (administration of law)
- ttbc French: justice
- ttbc Japanese: 正義 (せいぎ), 司法
- ttbc Latin: iustitia
- ttbc Norwegian: rettferdighet
- ttbc Portuguese: justiça
- ttbc Romanian: drept and
- ttbc Spanish: justicia
- ttbc Swedish: rätt, rättvisa
- ttbc Telugu: న్యాయం (nyaayam) (1, 2)
External links
Extensive Definition
Justice is a collective name which can be divided
into two broad perspectives. Just behavior; a concern for genuine
respect and treatment
which is to be regarded as fair and equal. The Administration of
Law; which ordains legislation composed by a judge or magistrate of a supreme
court to a country or state, with objectives to protect the
victims and pursue
the perpetrators lawfully. Prosperity and
distribution of wealth
towards the common people, is the most important aspect of justice
which greatly contributes to the wellbeing of society.
Variations of Justice
Utilitarianism is a form of consequentialism, where punishment is forward-looking. Justified by the ability to achieve future social benefits resulting in crime reduction, the moral worth of an action is determined by its outcome.Retributive
justice regulates proportionate response to crime proven by
lawful evidence, so that punishment is justly imposed and
considered as morally-correct and fully deserved. Retribution also
means prosperity, prosperity results in crime prevention.
The law of retaliation (lex
talionis) is a military theory of retributive justice, which
says that reciprocity should be equal to the wrong suffered; "life
for life, wound for wound, stripe for stripe." Distributive
justice is directed at the proper allocation of things -
wealth, power, reward, respect - between different people. A number
of important questions surrounding justice have been fiercely
debated over the course of western history: What is justice? What
does it demand of individuals and societies? What is the proper
distribution of wealth and resources in society: equal, meritocratic, according to status, or some
other arrangement? There is a myriad of possible answers to these
questions from divergent perspectives on the political and
philosophical spectrum.
Oppressive Law
exercises an authoritarian approach to legislation which is
"totally unrelated to justice", a tyrannical interpretation of law
is one in which the population lives under restriction from
unlawful legislation.
Some theorists, such as the classical Greeks,
conceive of justice as a virtue—a property of people, and
only derivatively of their actions and the institutions they
create. Others emphasize actions or institutions, and only
derivatively the people who bring them about. The source of justice
has variously been attributed to harmony, divine
command, natural law,
or human creation.
The importance of justice
Justice concerns the proper ordering of things
and persons within a
society. As a concept it
has been subject to philosophical, legal, and theological reflection and
debate throughout history. According to most
theories of justice, it is overwhelmingly important: John Rawls,
for instance, claims that "Justice is the first virtue of social
institutions, as truth is of systems of thought.": Justice can be
thought of as distinct from and more fundamental than benevolence, charity,
mercy, generosity or compassion. Research
conducted in 2003 at Emory
University, Georgia, involving Capuchin Monkeys demonstrated
that other cooperative animals also possess such a sense and that
"inequality
aversion may not be uniquely human." indicating that ideas of
fairness and justice are of an instinctual nature.
Justice as harmony
In his dialogue Republic, Plato uses Socrates to argue for justice which covers both the just person and the just city-state. Justice is a proper, harmonious relationship between the warring parts of the person or city. A person’s soul has three parts – spirit, resourcefulness and mindfulness. Similarly, a city has three parts – Socrates uses the parable of the chariot to illustrate his point: a chariot works as a whole because the two horses’ power is directed by the charioteer. Lovers of wisdom – philosophers, in one sense of the term – should rule because only they understand what is good. If one is ill, one goes to a doctor rather than a quack, because the doctor is expert in the subject of health. Similarly, one should trust one’s city to an expert in the subject of the good, not to a mere politician who tries to gain power by giving people what they want, rather than what’s good for them. Socrates uses the parable of the ship to illustrate this point: the unjust city is like a ship in open ocean, crewed by a powerful but drunken captain (the common people), a group of untrustworthy advisors who try to manipulate the captain into giving them power over the ship’s course (the politicians), and a navigator (the philosopher) who is the only one who knows how to get the ship to port. For Socrates, the only way the ship will reach its destination – the good – is if the navigator takes charge.Justice as divine command
Justice as a divine law is commanding , and indeed the whole of morality, is the authoritative command. Killing is wrong and therefore must be punished and if not punished what should be done?. There is a famous paradox called the Euthyphro dilemma which essentially asks: is something right because God commands it, or does God command it because it's right? If the former, then justice is arbitrary; if the latter, then morality exists on a higher order than God, who becomes little more than a passer-on of moral knowledge. Some Divine command advocates respond by pointing out that the dilemma is false: goodness is the very nature of God and is necessarily expressed in His commands.Justice as natural law
John Locke of the natural law believes that justice would become a natural law, it involves the system of punishments which are prone from choices. In this, it is similar to the laws of physics: in the same way as the Third of Newton's laws of Motion requires that for every action there must be an equal and opposite reaction, justice requires according individuals or groups what they actually deserve, merit, or are entitled to. Justice, on this account, is a universal and absolute concept: laws, principles, religions, etc., are merely attempts to codify that concept, sometimes with results that entirely contradict the true nature of justice.Justice as human creation
In contrast to the understandings canvassed so far, justice may be understood as a human creation, rather than a discovery of harmony, divine command, or natural law. This claim can be understood in a number of ways, with the fundamental division being between those who argue that justice is the creation of some humans, and those who argue that it is the creation of all humans.Justice as authoritative command
According to thinkers including Thomas Hobbes, justice is created by public, enforceable, authoritative rules, and injustice is whatever those rules forbid, regardless of their relation to morality. Justice is created, not merely described or approximated, by the command of an absolute sovereign power. This position has some similarities with divine command theory (see above), with the difference that the state (or other authority) replaces God.Justice as trickery
In Republic, the character Thrasymachus argues that justice is the interest of the strong: merely a name for whatever the powerful or cunning ruler has managed to impose on the people, to his or her own advantage. Nietzsche, in contrast, argues that justice is part of the slave-morality of the weak many, rooted in their resentment of the strong few, and intended to keep the noble man down. In Human, All Too Human he states that, "there is no eternal justice."Justice as mutual agreement
According to thinkers in the social contract tradition, justice is derived from the mutual agreement of everyone concerned; or, in many versions, from what they would agree to under hypothetical conditions including equality and absence of bias. This account is considered further below, under ‘Justice as fairness’.Justice as a subordinate value
According to utilitarian thinkers including John Stuart Mill, justice is not as fundamental as we often think. Rather, it is derived from the more basic standard of rightness, consequentialism: what is right is what has the best consequences (usually measured by the total or average welfare caused). So, the proper principles of justice are those which tend to have the best consequences. These rules may turn out to be familiar ones such as keeping contracts; but equally, they may not, depending on the facts about real consequences. Either way, what is important is those consequences, and justice is important, if at all, only as derived from that fundamental standard. Mill tries to explain our mistaken belief that justice is overwhelmingly important by arguing that it derives from two natural human tendencies: our desire to retaliate against those who hurt us, and our ability to put ourselves imaginatively in another’s place. So, when we see someone harmed, we project ourselves into her situation and feel a desire to retaliate on her behalf. If this process is the source of our feelings about justice, that ought to undermine our confidence in them.Theories of distributive justice
Theories of distributive justice need to answer
three questions:
- What goods are to be distributed? Is it to be wealth, power, respect, some combination of these things?
- Between what entities are they to be distributed? Humans (dead, living, future), sentient beings, the members of a single society, nations?
- What is the proper distribution? Equal, meritocratic, according to social status, according to need?
Distributive justice theorists generally do not
answer questions of who has the right to enforce a particular
favored distribution.
This section describes some widely-held theories
of distributive justice, and their attempts to answer these
questions.
Egalitarianism
According to the egalitarian, goods should be distributed equally. This basic view can be elaborated in many different ways, according to what goods are to be distributed – wealth, respect, opportunity – and what they are to be distributed equally between – individuals, families, nations, races, species. Commonly-held egalitarian positions include demands for equality of opportunity and for equality of outcome.Giving people what they deserve
In one sense, all theories of distributive justice claim that everyone should get what he or she deserves. Where they diverge is in disagreeing about the basis of desert. The main distinction is between, on one hand, theories which argue that the basis of just desert is something held equally by everyone and therefore derive egalitarian accounts of distributive justice; and, on the other hand, theories which argue that the basis of just desert is unequally distributed on the basis of, for instance, hard work, and therefore derive accounts of distributive justice according to which some should have more than others. This section deals with some popular theories of the second type.According to meritocratic theories, goods,
especially wealth and social status, should be distributed to match
individual merit, which is usually understood as some combination
of talent and hard work. According to needs-based theories, goods,
especially such basic goods as food, shelter and medical care,
should be distributed to meet individuals’ basic needs
for them. Marxism can be
regarded as a needs-based theory on some readings of Marx’s slogan,
‘From each according to his ability, to each according to his
needs’. According to contribution-based theories, goods should be
distributed to match an individual's contribution to the overall
social good.
Fairness
In his A Theory of Justice, John Rawls used a social contract argument to show that justice, and especially distributive justice, is a form of fairness: an impartial distribution of goods. Rawls asks us to imagine ourselves behind a veil of ignorance which denies us all knowledge of our personalities, social statuses, moral characters, wealth, talents and life plans, and then asks what theory of justice we would choose to govern our society when the veil is lifted, if we wanted to do the best that we could for ourselves. We don’t know who in particular we are, and therefore can’t bias the decision in our own favour. So, the decision-in-ignorance models fairness, because it excludes selfish bias. Rawls argues that each of us would reject the utilitarian theory of justice that we should maximize welfare (see below) because of the risk that we might turn out to be someone whose own good is sacrificed for greater benefits for others. Instead, we would endorse Rawls’s two principles of justice:- 1. Each person is to have an equal right to the most extensive
total system of equal basic liberties compatible with a similar
system of liberty for all.
- 2. Social and economic inequalities are to be arranged so that they are both
-
- a) to the greatest benefit of the least advantaged, consistent
with the just savings principle, and
- b) attached to offices and positions open to all under conditions of fair equality of opportunity.
- a) to the greatest benefit of the least advantaged, consistent
with the just savings principle, and
This imagined choice justifies these principles
as the principles of justice for us, because we would agree to them
in a fair decision procedure. Rawls’s theory distinguishes two
kinds of goods – (1) liberties
and (2) social and economic goods, i.e. wealth, income and power –
and applies different distributions to them – equality between
citizens for (1), equality unless inequality improves the position
of the worst off for (2).
Having the right history
Robert Nozick’s influential critique of Rawls argues that distributive justice is not a matter of the whole distribution matching an ideal pattern, but of each individual entitlement having the right kind of history. It is just that a person has some good (especially, some property right) if and only if he or she came to have it by a history made up entirely of events of two kinds:- 1. Just acquisition, especially by working on unowned things;
and
- 2. Just transfer, that is free gift, sale or other agreement, but not theft.
On the basis of this theory of distributive
justice, Nozick argues that all attempts to redistribute goods
according to an ideal pattern, without the consent of their owners,
are theft. In particular, redistributive
taxation is theft.
Welfare-maximization
According to the utilitarian, justice requires the maximization of the total or average welfare across all relevant individuals. This may require sacrifice of some for the good of others, so long as everyone’s good is taken impartially into account. Utilitarianism, in general, argues that the standard of justification for actions, institutions, or the whole world, is impartial welfare consequentialism, and only indirectly, if at all, to do with rights, property, need, or any other non-utilitarian criterion. These other criteria might be indirectly important, to the extent that human welfare involves them. But even then, such demands as human rights would only be elements in the calculation of overall welfare, not uncrossable barriers to action.Theories of retributive justice
Theories of retributive justice are concerned
with punishment for
wrongdoing, and need to answer three questions:
- why punish?
- who should be punished?
- what punishment should they receive?
Utilitarianism
According to the utilitarian, as already noted, justice requires the maximization of the total or average welfare across all relevant individuals. Punishment is bad treatment of someone, and therefore can’t be good in itself, for the utilitarian. But punishment might be a necessary sacrifice which maximizes the overall good in the long term, in one or more of three ways:- Deterrence. The credible threat of punishment might lead people to make different choices; well-designed threats might lead people to make choices which maximize welfare.
- Rehabilitation. Punishment might make bad people into better ones. For the utilitarian, all that ‘bad person’ can mean is ‘person who’s likely to cause bad things (like suffering) ’. So, utilitarianism could recommend punishment which changes someone such that he or she is less likely to cause bad things.
- Security. Perhaps there are people who are irredeemable causers of bad things. If so, imprisoning them might maximize welfare by limiting their opportunities to cause harm.
Retributivism
The retributivist will think the utilitarian's argument disastrously mistaken. If someone does something wrong, we must respond to it, and to him or her, as an individual, not as a part of a calculation of overall welfare. To do otherwise is to disrespect him or her as an individual human being. If the crime had victims, it is to disrespect them, too. Wrongdoing must be balanced or made good in some way, and so the criminal deserves to be punished. Retributivism emphasizes retribution – payback – rather than maximization of welfare. Like the theory of distributive justice as giving everyone what he or she deserves (see above), it links justice with desert. It says that all guilty people, and only guilty people, deserve appropriate punishment. This matches some strong intuitions about just punishment: that it should be proportional to the crime, and that it should be of only and all of the guilty. However, it is sometimes argued that retributivism is merely revenge in disguise. Despite this criticism, there are numerous differences between retribution and revenge: the former is impartial, has a scale of appropriateness and corrects a moral wrong, whereas the latter is personal, unlimited in scale, and often corrects a slight.further Deontological
ethics
Institutions
In an imperfect world, institutions are required
to instantiate ideals of justice, however imperfectly. These
institutions may be justified by their approximate instantiation of
justice, or they may be deeply unjust when compared with ideal
standards — consider the institution of slavery. Justice is an ideal
which the world fails to live up to, sometimes despite good
intentions, sometimes disastrously. The question of institutive
justice raises issues of
legitimacy, procedure,
codification and
interpretation,
which are considered by legal theorists and by philosophers
of law.
Another definition of justice is an independent
investigation of truth. In a court room, lawyers, the judge and the
jury are supposed to be independently investigating the truth of an
alleged crime. In physics, a group of physicists examine data and
theoretical concepts to consult on what might be the truth or
reality of a phenomenon.
See also
- Criminal justice
- Ethics
- Global justice
- Just war
- Justice (economics)
- Morality
- Social justice
- Teaching for social justice
- Commutative justice
- Corrective justice
- Distributive justice
- Restorative justice
- Retributive justice
References
Bibliography and further reading
- Barzilai Gad, Communities and Law: Politics and Cultures of Legal Identities (Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press, 2003).
- Brian Barry, Theories of Justice (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1989).
- Harry Brighouse, Justice (Cambridge: Polity Press, 2004).
- Anthony Duff & David Garland eds, A Reader on Punishment (Oxford: OUP, 1994).
- Colin Farrelly, An Introduction to Contemporary Political Theory (London: Sage, 2004).
- David Gauthier, Morals By Agreement (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1986).
- Robert E. Goodin & Philip Pettit eds, Contemporary Political Philosophy: An anthology (2nd edition, Malden Mass.: Blackwell, 2006), Part III.
- Ted Honderich, Punishment: The supposed justifications (London: Hutchinson & Co., 1969).
- Will Kymlicka, Contemporary Political Philosophy: An introduction (2nd edition, Oxford: OUP, 2002).
- Nicola Lacey, State Punishment (London: Routledge, 1988).
- John Stuart Mill, Utilitarianism in On Liberty and Other Essays ed. John Gray (Oxford: OUP, 1991).
- Robert Nozick, Anarchy, State, and Utopia (Oxford: Blackwell, 1974).
- Plato, Republic trans. Robin Waterfield (Oxford: OUP, 1994).
- John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (revised edition, Oxford: OUP, 1999).
- David Schmidtz, Elements of Justice (New York: CUP, 2006).
- Peter Singer ed., A Companion to Ethics (Oxford: Blackwell, 1993), Part IV.
- C.L. Ten, Crime, Guilt, and Punishment: A philosophical introduction (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1987).
External links
- Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy entries:
- Distributive justice, by Julian Lamont.
- Justice as a virtue, by Michael Slote.
- Punishment, by Hugo Adam Bedau.
- Video:Balkan Justice
justice in Catalan: Justícia
justice in Czech: Spravedlnost
justice in Welsh: Cyfiawnder
justice in Danish: Retfærdighed
justice in German: Gerechtigkeit
justice in Spanish: Justicia
justice in Estonian: Õiglus
justice in Finnish: Oikeus
justice in French: Justice
justice in Hebrew: צדק (מוסר)
justice in Indonesian: Keadilan
justice in Italian: Giustizia
justice in Japanese: 正義
justice in Korean: 정의
justice in Malayalam: നീതിന്യായം
justice in Dutch: Rechtvaardigheid
Synonyms, Antonyms and Related Words
Astraea, Dike, JP, Jupiter Fidius, Justice, Justitia, Minos, Nemesis, Rhadamanthus, Themis, actionability, applicability, arbiter, arbitrator, assured probity,
balance, beak, bencher, blamelessness, blindfolded
Justice, cardinal virtues, character, charity, cleanness, coequality, coextension, constitutional
validity, constitutionalism,
constitutionality,
correspondence,
court, critic, decency, detention, due process,
dueness, entitledness, entitlement, equality, equation, equilibrium, equipoise, equipollence, equiponderance, equitableness, equity, equivalence, equivalency, erectness, estimableness, evenness, expectation, fair play,
fair-mindedness, fairness, faith, fortitude, good character,
goodness, high ideals,
high principles, high-mindedness, his honor, his lordship, his
worship, honesty,
honor, honorableness, hope, identity, immaculacy, impartiality, imprisonment, incarceration, indicator, integrity, irreproachability,
irreproachableness,
judge, judger, judgment, judicatory, judicature, judicial process,
judiciary, judiciousness, jurisdiction, justiciability,
justifiable expectation, justness, law, lawfulness, legal form, legal
process, legalism,
legality, legitimacy, legitimateness, levelness, licitness, likeness, love, magistrate, meritedness, moderator, moral excellence,
moral strength, morality, natural virtues,
neutrality, nobility, objectiveness, objectivity, par, parallelism, parity, poise, principles, prison, probity, proportion, prudence, punishment, pureness, purity, rectitude, referee, reputability, respectability, right, righteousness, rightfulness, scope, stainlessness,
supernatural virtues, symmetry, temperance, the courts, the
law, theological virtues, umpire, unimpeachability,
unimpeachableness,
unspottedness,
uprightness,
upstandingness,
validity, virtue, virtuousness, worthiness